Social Interaction. Video-Based Studies of Human Sociality.
2018 VOL. 1, Issue 2
ISBN: 2446-3620
DOI: 10.7146/si.v1i2.110037
Objectivation practices[1]
Kenneth Liberman
Professor Emeritus, University of Oregon
Linkages between the early interactionist sociology of Simmel and Garfinkel’s ethnomethodology are explored, using illustrations drawn from the author’s research on coffee tasting, the debates of Tibetan scholar-monks, and players of board games. Garfinkel’s inquiries into the neglected objectivity of social facts are specified with concrete illustrations, and a model is developed to guide the investigation of some seminal topics in ethnomethodology. Discounting rational choice theory, voluntarism, and individualist models, this study offers an account of the objectivation practices that parties routinely employ when they collaborate in setting up an orderliness for their local affairs.
Sociology is accustomed to acknowledging three founding fathers – Durkheim, Marx, and Weber. Whenever a fourth founder is mentioned, that fourth person is usually Georg Simmel. In many ways Simmel is the thinker whose original contributions to sociology have had the most pertinence for the inquiries of ethnomethodology, and this is because he recognized that the mundane affairs of everyday life are foundational practices for society. Simmel (1959a: 315) calls the activity by which individuals find themselves operating cooperatively “sociation,” and he considers it to be a topic that is both fundamental and intractable (Simmel 1959: 324): “There is no perfectly clear technique for applying the fundamental sociological concept itself (that is, the concept of sociation).” Simmel’s idea of sociation can guide us so long as we recall Garfinkel’s (2006: 161) caution that a “rough statement doesn’t tell us what we’ve found; it tells us what to look for.”
What is this thing “sociation”? Simmel (1959a: 315) writes, “Sociation is the form (realized in innumerably different ways) in which individuals grow together into a unity.” How do people develop or discover a unified canvas for, in, and as their mundane social interaction? It is this collaborative search-and-discovery project that is the topic here. Under what conditions and to what extent are members able or unable to affect things? I am especially interested in inquiring about whether anybody at any time knows just what they’re doing. In other words, to what extent are persons engaged in sociation “actors” in the sense that they are able to control affairs in a deliberate fashion, and to what extent are they limited to responding to emerging patterns and rhythms that temporarily surface in the hubbub that surrounds them? Simmel (1959b: 342) cautions us that the real action of sociation “does not consist of cognitions but of concrete processes and actual situations.” While much social science is preoccupied with concepts and cognitions, ethnomethodology has turned its attention to the most concrete, immanent things of the world.
It is for certain that I do not want to proceed by defining sociation and then to proceed from that definition. Sociation is too deeply embedded in our lives to be treated in a heavy-handed way; instead, it requires being discovered just-as-it-is and then specified “from itself in the very way in which it shows itself from itself” (Heidegger 1962: 58). Simmel only named it; he himself did not yet know what it was. Consider what he said about the obscure “minor” social forms that are at work in sociation, which he contrasts with the “major” or more macro social forms[2] that have captured the attention of most social scientists: [2]
"On the basis of these major formations – which constitute the traditional subject matter of social science – it would be entirely impossible to piece together the real life of society as we encounter it in our experience… It is really these minor forms that bring about society as we know it.” (Simmel 1959: 327)
I accept that these minor social forms are ethnomethodology’s fundamental data.
Phenomenology has informed these inquiries from the outset, and we should recall that Edmund Husserl and Georg Simmel were friends and read each other’s works carefully.
These well-used books authored by Simmel, which today sit on the shelves of Husserl’s books at the Husserl Archives in Leuven, demonstrate that Husserl took Simmel seriously and allow us to deduce that while ethnomethodology has learned a good deal from phenomenology, it can also be said that the sociological interest, and most importantly the interest in studying sociation that was later sustained and expanded by ethnomethodology, had some influence upon phenomenology. We should also not forget that Simmel is correct that these mundane social forms are obscure and that it is not easy to capture the details of these “everyday formations.” Ethnomethodology has made capturing these concrete local details into a discipline.
For the most part mainstream sociology has been disappointed with, and even resistant to, the messy but real details identified and described by ethnomethodological researchers. Daston and Alison (2010) located in 19th-century physics an illustration that is paradigmatic for our dilemma. From 1875 to 1894 a conscientious physicist, Arthur Worthington, had been making careful drawings of how different liquid media splatter when they hit a hard surface. In 1894, Worthington attempted to use the new art of photography to capture the details of how drops of various liquid substances splatter, because he believed that with photography he could capture those precise details even more perfectly. Much to his surprise, the real splattering was more disorganized and less coherent than what was presented by his ideal depictions. Daston and Alison (2010: 12 & 14) present the contrasting representations. First, here are the sketches of liquid media:
And then, the photographs of liquid media:
Worthington was disappointed that the real world offered less order than did his ideal representations in much the same way that mainstream sociology is dissatisfied with the results of ethnomethodological research.
In the context of a Simmelian outlook, let us consider the aphorism invoked frequently by Garfinkel (1967: 33), “The policy is recommended that any social setting be viewed as self-organizing.” What does Garfinkel mean? In effect, it is a criticism of cognitivism in social science. Intersubjective affairs are unpredictable, and in spite of the many social scientists who imagine that our lives are more rationally motivated than they really are, events largely run themselves. This is an important change of perspective, and a postmodern one. As Garfinkel used to say, we have moved beyond rationalist just-so stories. The “reciprocal stimulation” that occurs (Simmel’s term, 1959a: 328) in intersubjective affairs is so dynamic that much of the time the participants gaze upon the affairs in wonder, barely able to anticipate where things might go next but keen to learn where that is, as soon as it happens. According to Simmel (1959b: 343) there is a necessary incompleteness to each situation, and this keeps participants anticipating.
Events are continuously in flux, and there are no time-outs. The flux of ordinary affairs keeps confounding us by exceeding our efforts to render those affairs orderly. And new rules are born every minute as part of our efforts to tame the situation or turn it to our advantage. As Simmel (1959: 328) tells us, “At each moment such threads are spun, dropped, taken up again, displaced by others, interwoven by others. These interactions among the atoms of society are accessible only to psychological microscopy, as it were.” It is ethnomethodology’s interest to provide microscopic scrutiny and to identify the endless entanglements of these recurring dislocations, which in ethnomethodology go by the following names: “no timeout,” “first time through,” “authochthonous,” “in vivo,” and my favorite, “the endless, ongoing, contingent accomplishments.”
In the 1960s and early 1970s some mainstream British sociologists dismissed ethnomethodology as a form of Californian subjectivism. This upset Garfinkel, first because never in his life did he think of himself as a Californian (in fact, he always hated the place); and second, because he was not a bit interested in subjectivity – already in his dissertation he had written about “the sterilities of subjectivity” (2006: 151). Instead, he called for ethnomethodologists to pay close attention to “the neglected objectivity” of social facts, and this is the principal clue that motivates the present essay.
Garfinkel (2002: 189) also proposed that, “Work-site practices are developingly objective and developingly accountable.” I am trying to elucidate just what is meant by “developingly objective.” In our efforts to tame our data, we must never lose the site of this “developingly,” and most probably even ethnomethodologists have yet to fully appreciate the actual flux of affairs. Like other people, ethnomethodologists are preoccupied with orderliness and with converting the flux of affairs into something more predictable, and this can lead them to proposing more order than is actually there. In everyday life most actors desire orderliness in their affairs, but they are unsure just how to accomplish it, and they end up stumbling into any ready-at-hand solution that presents itself in the course of their affairs. Moreover, people rarely seek a totalistic organization – they are not sociologists after all. Sometimes their interest in organization extends only as far as being able to cross the street.
As Garfinkel has taught us, members pick up from the looks of the world a method for organizing local affairs, and then they display for each other how such a method (a rule, a place in line, an opinion…) can be used to accomplish some orderliness. In other words, ethnomethods are instructable matters: people teach them to each other. But it is important to emphasize that in most cases these methods are stumbled upon, spotted serendipitously amidst the spectacle of the world. Only rarely are they planned with foresight; or, if they are planned such plans never quite work out in the way that is anticipated. That is the reason people to pay close attention to their mundane affairs, and it was this close attention that people pay that most captured Garfinkel’s imagination.
Even though these methods that people stumble upon and teach other assist them in organizing the orderliness of their local affairs, people still become entangled inside the local circumstances that these methods produce (Garfinkel 2002: 65). What has been astonishing in my research is to keep rediscovering that the ethnomethods lead the people rather than the people designing the methods by cognitive decision. Every line of communication becomes an entanglement, and yet the contingent circumstances set into play by these entanglements keep providing parties with further resources for organizing local orderlinesses by bricolage. Sometimes an ethnomethod can involve the use of any material thing that is at hand, which eases the task of organizing a local orderliness. By “a material thing” I mean things like blackboards, gameboards, Powerpoint, etc., but I also mean things like a phrase or a term that serves to get people onto the same page. Any device that is at hand can be made to serve the interests of cooperating parties in developing that unity of which Simmel is speaking.
I offer the following illustration in order to make more clear this important point about ethnomethods leading the people rather than people leading the ethnomethods. Professional coffee tasters are faced with the naturally occurring task of rendering the wildness of the tastes of coffee more orderly and subject to remembering, recording, communicating, considering further, etc. They work to locate, identify and describe the principal tastes by developing a few taste descriptors that can carry their discoveries and effectively communicate them to other personnel in the coffee industry. The meaning of some of these descriptors is simple and obvious, such as “chocolate;” but others, like “balanced,” “round,” and “clean,” are not so well defined, and the descriptors function in part by collecting whatever a drinker is able to discover while examining the taste in a cup under the guidance of the descriptor. The sense and reference of these descriptors can expand and contract, and much of the important work of professional tasters is to tame the meaning of these descriptors so that they can be made reliable and assist the work of making taste more objective and precise.
To aid them in such work, coffee tasters use evaluation charts that facilitate the translation of tastes into numerical, and thus hopefully objective, representations. These charts or schedules place something tangible in the hands of professional tasters, which they can then use to make their activities orderly, and I and my colleague Giolo Fele of the Università di Trento have spent several years studying how these charts are used, one sample of which is included here:
We used a simplified version of this chart to afford student lay tasters some focus for their evaluations. While our hope was that these charts would allow their thinking and discussion to be made more publicly observable to us and require them to verbalize their thinking so that we as researchers could follow their thinking more carefully, it did not work that way: instead of being used as a tool for exploring taste, the charts became a device for creating an orderliness that facilitated their being able to get on the same page in the social interaction that accompanied their tasting. The tasting itself and the flavors that the tasting identified, were relegated to a subsidiary status. In the end, the rating charts ended up governing the interaction not because it assisted their tasting but because it assisted them to organize a local orderliness for their social interaction and so render their interaction predictable and less risky. This is significant because it demonstrates that the cooperating parties’ immanent concerns with orderliness can have priority over the substantive objectives that their collaborative work was intended to address. Through a wide swathe of ethnomethodological and conversation-analytic research, what is most immanent in local interactional work supersedes more obvious items of business that may have motivated the social action in the first place.
Let us examine how this worked
here. The first of these five short clips shows the tasting forms being passed
out to the lay student tasters (not professional tasters) and displays their
initial examination of the charts:
The Numerators 1
With these forms in hand, the lay tasters proceed through the first of three rounds of tasting, one for each cup of coffee they are evaluating:
The Numerators 2
Despite their task, they discuss flavors only briefly. Given the tasting schedule, they quickly reduce their evaluation to a numeral for entry on their form. The form affords them the opportunity to render their interaction orderly and to quite literally arrive on the same page. As we can learn from The Numerators 2 clip, which does not require a translation, they quickly adopt a protocol of discussing only numbers. How does that come to be the accepted protocol? That is never discussed by the tasters, and no proposal about doing so is mentioned. The course of affairs themselves simply lead the participants into what is, practically speaking, a numeration-only ethnomethod for providing orderliness for their work of tasting, and their work quickly becomes reduced to the task of filling out the numeral-based form.
Even when their numerical
evaluations differ, they do not discuss those differences in terms of flavors:
they speak almost exclusively about numbers, and this is so even while they
are uncertain what is the meaning of those numbers. They are distracted
from the serious work of tasting by the apparent orderliness of numeration.
There is no calibration of these numbers, which is a necessary and vital step
in professional tastings, at least until the second round when the naturally
occurring comparisons between the first cup and the second cup allow their
numbers to acquire more specific meaning. In the second round they taste their
second coffee (The Numerators 3), and they numerate with more confidence, and it
seems that they appreciate the safety that hiding behind these numbers affords
them. Some categories that are given ratings, such as “balance,” are things
about which they have little understanding. Their assessments regarding
sweetness (dolcezza) and velvet texture (vellutato) display a
gross kind of evaluating, and the tasters generate their numbers with minimal
discussion, often nothing more than a “Si!” (yes). The Numerators 3 By the third coffee that is tasted
(The Numerators 4), the comparison practice has become more refined, and the robust
character of their practice of numeration is evident in the fact that they
discuss only numbers, and their growing confidence with their ethnomethod obscures
the fact that their method is facile.
The Numerators 4 The tasters have barely learned a thing
about the coffees. What is more, because they are not really discussing the
tastes they are locating, they are unable to teach each other anything either. Here
is a translation for part of their discussion in the final clip, “The Numerators 5” (5:16-27), during which they are assessing the “sweetness”
aspect of the coffee without ever considering what it can be for a drink like
coffee, which is characteristically bitter, to be sweet. Their numbers gain
some practical currency by virtue of contrasting the evaluations from the earlier
two rounds of tasting with the present coffee. They decide upon a number, and
then proceed directly to the next category: A Il primo era 5. The
first was 5. B E secondo? And
the second? A Secondo 9. The
second 9. C Un 7! A
7! A O.K. … “Vellutato”?
… The tasters have lost the phenomenon
(Garfinkel 2002: 264-67). Importantly, and as Garfinkel might have observed,
they have not lost the phenomenon in any which way, they have lost it specifically
because of their use, as an ethnomethod, of the “metrological” work (Garfinkel
2002: 284) of their numerating. By metrological Garfinkel is referring to the
use of measurement practices for providing a definitive characterization of the
inherent properties of the phenomena under examination and for providing an
orderliness for their practical work on any local occasion (Garfinkel 2002:
270). In the final clip, the tasters have even become satirists regarding the cavalier
character of their numerating: note that the rating of “seven” (“un sette!”)
is offered in the manner of self-satire. The Numerators 5 They have lost track of their agenda. They
may not even have had an agenda, but were simply engaged in looking to the
others and waiting for the situation to present them with an agenda. If we do presume
that they had an agenda, which was to evaluate the coffees they were drinking,
then they have lost track of that objective. They are caught up and become entangled
in the very metrological procedures that they are using for providing
orderliness to the local occasion. They have become “tangled in circumstantiality”
(Garfinkel 2002: 65). Examples of becoming tangled in
circumstantiality abound, and as soon as I noticed this phenomenon I have been
discovering it in nearly every bit of data I have collected during my various
research projects. Let me offer another case here: when people ask a passerby
for street directions it can happen that the reply includes many details that
are not helpful for learning the direction and that distract the parties who
are asking for directions so much (i.e. so entangle them in peripheral matters)
that they fail to talk about, and occasionally even fail to recognize
themselves, the inadequacy of the directions that were elicited. For instance,
in some case studies that my students and I collected in Buenos Aires, two
pedestrians walking across a part of the city asked a passerby, “How do we get
to Lezama Park?” The passerby replied, “Take the 168 or 64 bus from Pueyrredón Street.”
Instead of their replying, “But we’re planning to walk,” in order to elicit
advice that would be more pertinent to them, in an effort to be cooperative the
parties simply repeated the last few syllables of the passerby’s utterance, “en
Pueyrredón,” along with an accompanying nod of their heads followed by a friendly
“Gracias.” That is, they became caught up inside the agenda of the passerby and his reply, from which they were either unable or unwilling
to extricate themselves. One might say that they showed deference to the
autochthonic, emerging social structures of the occasion. Very many instances
of soliciting directions turn out this way: the response is a divergence from
what the parties intended to ask, and yet parties do not ask again, or try to reformulate
their inquiry. The immanent requirements of the conversation distract the parties
from the task of securing the needed information. Garfinkel studied under Parsons, who in his
sociological practice employed what had become sociology’s standard trope of
the homunculus: people were turned into puppets, and the only thoughts they were
allowed to have were those that the sociologist was able to stuff into their
heads. The direction away from individualism, and rationalism, that we have
been taking for three generations now has become clear. In contrast to Talcott
Parsons, Schutz was insistent upon not being satisfied with theorizing society
and turned to examining some of the lived realities of everyday life. In
contrast to Schutz, Garfinkel came to mostly avoid even phenomenological
theorizing and turned strictly to studies of naturally occurring activities for
direction, even to the point of being accused of being an empiricist (Attewell
1974). In place of “production practices” Garfinkel began to speak of scenes as
“self-organizing” (and there is an echo of Parsons in this), which are
situations in which no matter how skillful members may be, they are not really in
charge of things. Finding one’s path through the
complexities of our quotidian life requires considerable ability on the part of
members, and ethnomethodologists like to examine each one of these artful
practices, much in the way a bird-watcher is keenly observant and eager to
identify and describe each newly discovered aspect of avian behavior. But in spite
of their artful practices, members proceed myopically – their vision is local,
even more local than local. This “more local than local” is what Husserl intended
by his word “immanent” in the definition of phenomenology he offers in Ideas
(1962: 161): “a pure descriptive theory of the immanent formations of
consciousness”. We are constantly attempting to find our bearings, and much of
the time no one is in control. The ethnomethodological investigation
proceeds from the immanent looks of the world from the perspectives of the
members trying to find their way together. Here I investigate how events
organize themselves, and I try to appraise to what extent and under what
conditions members are able to affect things. Parsons presumed too much. Schutz
presumed too much. And on a few occasions even Garfinkel presumed too much. Since
we are academics, it is difficult for us to shed our rationalist blinders. In an unpublished 1962 paper,
in which Garfinkel first laid out his plan for Studies in Ethnomethodology,
he said that he would “treat … methodological interests of the members of
society as objects of theoretical sociological inquiry” (Psathas 2004). To what
extent do people really have deliberate, planned ahead of time, “methodological
interests”? They can have them, to be sure, but my studies reveal that
it is more common that they do not know what they are doing until a routine is
put into play as a collaborative and autochthonous event. In a 1965 version of the paper
(typescript), which was delivered at the University of Oregon, Garfinkel said,
“Persons, in the ways in which they are members of ordinary
arrangements, are engaged in the artful accomplishment of the rational
properties of indexical particulars.” At that early stage of ethnomethodology I
think we possibly idealized what was rational activity. It turns out that
rational activity is not nearly as rational as we were thinking at the time.
The notion “members” already undoes some of the individualist, deliberate,
controlling aspects of rational activity, in that it is an admission that
people are acting as a collective. Deliberate, voluntarist, rational planning
is not unknown, but mostly the events move too fast for planning to be very
effective, a phenomenon that always impressed Aaron Cicourel (1974), who
insisted in his field research that the basic structures of interaction were
always in the process of emerging. Once Garfinkel became absorbed
in studying scenic practices, i.e. in “studies,” he came to rely less upon
social phenomenological idealizations of decision-making and sense-assembly and
to emphasize more the authochthonous and tendentious nature of those affairs.
In the last year of his life, when he once casually used the phrase “production
practices” in a conversation with me at his home, I criticized the term
“production” by suggesting that it was too voluntarist. I said that yes an
orderliness gets produced, but much of the time no one is in charge, and the
orderliness that ends up governing affairs can be one that no one had in mind
in advance, so “produced” is not always an apt term to describe what is going
on. Garfinkel replied thoughtfully, “Yes, you’re right. Perhaps we need to give
up on the term ‘production.’” Even at an early stage Garfinkel (2006 (1948),
156) intuited this: “One runs the risk of
assuming a rational actor, and we wish to avoid this assumption;” and in the
same study he downplays “purposeful calculation” (160). So then he asked me
what term I would use instead. I replied that there is “congregational
work oriented to finding an orderliness,” but that we have yet to identify it or
describe it adequately. This essay is my attempt to move the ball further down
the field. 5.1. Intersubjectivity Aron Gurwitsch, a student of Edmund Husserl who was
brought to the US by Gurwitsch’s colleague Alfred Schutz, wrote about
“intersubjectively concatenated and interlocking experiences,” (Gurwitsch 1966:
432) but this too is only a phrase and not yet a specification. While
ethnomethodology has learned a great deal from Husserl’s theory of
intersubjectivity (elaborated for the social sciences by Schutz and Gurwitsch),
ethnomethodology has also learned that most of these intersubjective activities
are not necessarily planned, or necessarily conceptual. All three of these
phenomenologists acknowledged the importance of signs, but their reading of the
work of signs, while seminal, is perhaps too logical and conceptual to fully capture
the role played by the brute materiality of the signs that come to be possessed
in common by interacting parties, and that get used by parties to organize the
local orderliness of their affairs. Careful studies of micro-interaction have
revealed that these interconcatenations can occur before the meaning of
the signs being shared by parties is settled. Social phenomenological
perspectives that presume that a meaning always comes first, individual
consciousness by individual consciousness, and only then comes to be “shared”
or “negotiated” are mistaken. In fact, the meaning may never get
settled, should not get settled, and in most instances cannot get settled. Innumerable
social interactions take place during which parties operate with different
understandings of the same signs, or even with no understanding at all. This
situation is commonplace. It is our lives. How do the objective structures
of social interaction get worked out before those structures receive
their contents? Merleau-Ponty (1962: xx) offers us a clue: “Sense is revealed where my own and other
people’s paths intersect and engage each other like gears.” It seems that the course of affairs
serendipitously guides the participants to the competent coordinated social
interaction they seek. Ethnomethodology and conversation analysis share the
common aim of tracking just how these gears engage each other, that is, how the
microstructures can lead the parties to their solutions. In this sense, intersubjectivity
is more objective than it is subjective, and so perhaps a new name for
the phenomenon should be sought. The important point here is that the events
lead the way, and parties must continuously adapt to local structures that are always
emerging, with no timeouts. This perspective is not in any way a resurrection
of treating parties as judgmental dopes; rather, it proposes a specification of
what it is that artful practices consist of. The importance of members’ work is
not being diminished, but the idea that members always fully cognize just what
they are doing is discounted. Members are not Robinson Crusoes who know, as
individuals, each next step of what they are doing. The artfulness of their
organizing an orderliness is to be found in how they apply the tools that get
objectivated during the natural course of interaction and how they place them into
service for the local tasks of providing for intelligibility, order,
predictability, efficacy, and every other contingency of coordinating their
activities: it is not that they always know these ahead of the “inside-with”
tendentious life of their work. 5.2. Tendentiousness The “artful accomplishment” and artful practices that
were the focus of Garfinkel’s studies are not always highly planned doings;
rather, they involve members’ keen but opportunistic watchfulness for any
object that can be rigged to work for structuring the local affairs, or even
more basically, that can help them stay out of trouble, which is frequently the
first priority of parties on any occasion. In the early days of
ethnomethodology, we used to speak of society as “a floating crap game,” an
image that captures well the flux of our quotidian affairs. A social event
leads itself, and situations
are continuously in flux. Proust (2002: 60), observing the ever-changing and
fluid rules of warfare during his account of the First World War, writes, “War
is no exception to good old Hegel’s laws. It is in a state of perpetual
becoming,” and even today our generals complain that we are always fighting the
last war, which leaves us unprepared for fighting the present one. Like that,
“rules” are not as stable as sociologists once imagined them to be, and each
application of a rule happens first-time-through. More than to principles (which
operate as resources, much the way that rules do), peoples’ sight extends to
what is “next” and not much further than that. Our sight is myopic. Things may tend
toward a direction, but usually that direction is neither clear nor distinct. This
is its tendentiousness. It is such a “close-in” phenomenon that careless social
analysts can miss it. This can also go by the name of “the looks of the world.” In the Boston Seminars[3] Garfinkel spoke of “the
phenomenon as the interior course of its own production.” In other words, an
event drives itself with its own momentum; however, it may not be clear where an
event is heading. It is not that the people are not involved, but society moves
in accord with its own momentum. This is closely related with the “inside-with”
that Garfinkel speaks of in Ethnomethodology’s Program (2002: 271). People
can only work with the practical objectivities that emerge within each
occasion, and one thing leads
to a next. In our absorption inside the local circumstances of each occasion,
memories are short. Doug Macbeth, from who I learned to better appreciate this
notion of tendentiousness, informs me that, “It is heard in a first
which second is called for, and every present turn instructs what it calls for
next.” It is this “nextness” and the horizon of this nextness that identifies
the tendentiousness of affairs, and this is related to the flux of social interaction
that I am describing. Put in a different way, people
pattern after each other, and they pick up ways of formulating and ways of
knowing that follow from the previous speakers. However, they frequently misread
a previous speaker and so inadvertently carry affairs off to a new hinterland
that was not anticipated by anyone. The “floating crap game” aspect is that people
must pay attention to these new hinterlands that keep arriving on the scene. Macbeth also reminded me of a
passage from an important essay by Michael Moerman and Harvey Sacks (1988: 180-186),
“On Understanding,” where they are emphatic that turn-taking systems work “one utterance at a time.”
The immanence of local affairs always presses upon one, and what is most proximal
is the thing that grabs our attention. We are oriented to a “next,” but there
is only one “next” at a time! This limits the opportunities for longer-term
organizing, and solutions can become restricted to what is close at hand, to what
is immanent, without the bigger aims of social science always playing the
principal role. In short, we are overwhelmed by the swarm of the quotidian
events that keep heading our way. When Moerman’s essay was republished in his 1988 book, Moerman had in the end come to recognize
that understanding was not as straightforward as they had been assuming. That
is to say, even two of the most brilliant of ethnomethodologists had been
over-rationalizing intersubjectivity. Reconsidering his title during a brief
“1987 Introduction,” Moerman recommended changing the wording of “understanding,”
which had already become “what is called ‘understanding’,” to the more accurate
“the events that pass or fail to pass as understanding,” which offers us a much
more open representation of affairs, in the very way that the affairs are
open for the participants. In making this move, Moerman acknowledges that
understanding can fail, and that it is not rational in the strict way that we may
like to assume and in the way that the “decision sciences” would have it today. Ordinary matters can be left
up in the air, with no one certain, which is why parties keep themselves
oriented to that next. Because utterances occur one at
a time, the activities that serve
to organize local orderlinesses also occur one at a time, which results in
everyone having to remain oriented to what next may be impending. In the
immanence of this experience, people become myopic in their preoccupation with
that next next that must be handled, to the point that larger-scale
interests are lost sight of and even forgotten. (One only needs to recall how
quickly we are able to lose the focus that motivates one of our own Google
searches.) While macrosociologists are looking for the big picture in the way Simmel
describes, and the phenomenologists are looking for the big theories, the
parties themselves are preoccupied with not much more than looking for that
next next, since that is what they need to survive in the interaction.
While that may be too mundane for macrosociologists and phenomenologists to become
motivated to invest much of their attention to such a topic, because it is
critical for parties it is critical for ethnomethodologists. The tendentiousness is the immanent
traction that people procure on matters, often guided by what appears to be most
readily communicable, i.e. by what can cause people to find themselves able to
operate on the same page. It is important to note that operating on the same
page is not necessarily the same thing as understanding meanings. Garfinkel
always insisted that accounts were “vague” and that they were subject to
“indefinite elaboration” (the etcetera principle). Here we must recall
Garfinkel’s often repeated warning: “There is nothing hidden inside of our
heads but brains.” The world is there in front of us, in the spectacle
we are sharing, and that is why thinking is mostly a public activity. “Tendentious,”
which I believe is a term Garfinkel did not use until the 1980s, is a way to
repair our being too cognitivist in our studies. It is an appreciation that
things run along to wherever they are heading, on their own, and we mostly are
left to discover them after the fact. This is not to suggest that we never try
to bring our focus to bear upon events, it is only to observe that much of the
time we do not yet have a comprehensive grasp of what we are doing. To assist us in our efforts to examine the
intricacies of this peculiar situation, at once curious and unavoidable, I
offer the topic of what I am calling “Objectivation,” after Husserl (1969: 34;
1970: 358-61; 1973: 199), Schutz (1967: 133-34), and Garfinkel (2006: 135). Objectivation
is the work of turning our thinking or activities into objects that are
publicly available for people to use for organizing the local orderlinesses of
their affairs. These objects can be notions or they can be actual physical
objects, or both. They have a materiality that allows them to sit there in the
spectacle, permitting parties to use them as focal points for their
collaborative attention, i.e. for getting everyone on the same page so that
they can commence the work of making their affairs orderly. They are the basic tools
at hand with which the participants can work cooperatively. Most importantly, one of my
discoveries is that people do not “construct” or “produce” these objects;
rather, the objects find their way to centerstage on their own. Even when
people do try to plan for them, parties are surprised by what they end up
becoming, even though it is typical that parties will avoid displaying any
surprise. By working “on their own” I mean that they have a ubiquitous temporal
sequence that works like this: Account → Confirmation → Objectivation → Disengagement There is not the space here to offer a
detailed theoretical explanation of accounts.[4]
This is a longstanding topic in ethnomethodology, although it is not always
fully understood, and much has been written about it. Instead, I will take
advantage of the multimedia aspect of this journal and offer some demonstrations
of naturally occurring interaction that illustrate what accounts are and how
they work in local occasions. Accounts only come to be adopted when they
are confirmed by the parties who are present when the account is
uttered, and this phenomenon seems to be well understood. Objectivation is
equally important for the social work that parties face (that is, for the
“sociality,” to use the term suggested by Simmel), even though the topic has
not been given the same attention that accounts and confirmation have received.
According to Simmel (1959b: 337), our subjective impressions “become objects as
they are transformed into fixed regularities and into a consistent picture.” Objectivation
is part of the way that parties come to produce the social “facts” about which
Durkheim spoke and which is still considered to be one of the principal topics for
sociological research.[5]
This stage of this temporal sequence serves to point us toward objectivation as
a radical phenomenon, by which I mean the endless, in situ work of
parties to provide themselves with the tools necessary for organizing an
orderliness for their situation. Especially, the gloss “objectivation” is
intended to emphasize the communicative work of producing a Durkheimian thing. It
should not be allowed to stand in for a study of that work but should help to guide
the analyst to just where that work is taking place. Absent the identification
and scrutiny of this collaborative public work, in its specifics, this step of
the model is good for nothing. Ignore the model, but do look for the local work
of producing the public object that affords a cohort of persons a means for
coordinating their actions. Disengagement involves a degree of social
amnesia that is applied to what has been objectivated. It is the activity by
which parties are able to render themselves unaware that the “facts” they have
adopted emerged within (“inside-with”) social processes in which they just had
a hand. This amnesia is necessary for the objectivated tool, thing,
ethnomethod, result, etc. to possess the moral status that is required if it is
to compel conformity. Nevertheless, the apparent cohort independence of what is
objectivated usually depends upon provision of some acknowledgement or public
ratification of this elevated status; disengagement contributes to providing
for the independence of what has been objectivated and for the “immortal”
character of the social facts, as Durkheim described. It permits parties to
sustain the illusion that the reality, as they acknowledge it, has fallen out
of the sky (perhaps not simultaneously with the Ten Commandments but shortly
thereafter) without their intimate participation, in just the way that my grade-school
librarian always managed to do with her rules (giving me the opportunity to
make many early studies of this phenomenon). Three illustrations of the model: Utilizing the resources of this multimedia
forum, video clips of three diverse cases of naturally occurring social
interaction are presented in order to specify, by way of illustration, each of
the first three of the components of my model.[6]
These short “studies” include Play in a Game-with-Rules, Tibetan Philosophical Debating
at a Buddhist university, and an Espresso-Tasting Session guided by a master
roaster. 6.1 Play in a Game-with-Rules The first illustration involves the
formulation and objectivation of a rule of play during a game called Aggravation.
The players are four students who had never played the game before. They are
completing their reading of the rules and are about to commence play. The
rules, of course, are unable to cover everything, and in our clip the players
deliberate what to do about dice that accidentally roll off the table and onto
the floor: The player on the
right (Player D) observes that the player who is rolling the die is shaking and
rolling the die with considerable energy, so she raises the matter of what to
do if the die should roll off the table. This is important because it can
happen that a player who likes the number on the die will accept that number as
the roll, but may try to re-roll if that number is not to the player’s liking. To
Player D’s question, the player second from the left (Player B) offers a
tentative assertion that carries the implication that if it is offensive there
should be a policy for handling the situation. Player D commences an account,
to the effect that such a person should be required to re-roll the die, and
Player B quickly (in fact, almost simultaneously) confirms that account.
Player B adds an observation that such a policy is in fact a rule made up by
themselves, to which the female player next to him (Player C) chuckles, implying
cooperation. Player A at the far left, the potentially offending player, comments
upon what has transpired by jesting that the policy has become a “house rule,” at
which Player C laughs. The transcript picks up the interaction from 0.19
seconds, approximately halfway through the clip: A “house rule” is more common in
cardplaying than it is in boardgame playing, and it is a rule that is not
included in the formal rules or rulebook but is required by what Garfinkel
(1974) has called the game-furnished conditions and is adopted by the casino or
house at which the game of cards is being played. It more or less enjoys the
same status as a rule in a rulebook or instructions. While in this clip it is
an artful jest, a bit of humor that contributes to the players’ enjoyment of
the play, it also is a move that effectively objectivates the policy so
that it stands as a fact of their play beyond the reach of any individual
player. This had consequences for their play later when a player who attempted
to move the piece in conformity with the number on a die that had rolled onto
the floor was overruled by this objectivated policy. 6.2 Tibetan Philosophical Debating The debating
is in Tibetan, and viewers will need to consult the transcript of the
interaction for the English; the transcript can be coordinated with the video
by consulting the timings. In what is typical for these Tibetan dialectics, the
account provided by the debater who is standing is offered first in a positive
form, then in a negative form, and once again in a positive and conclusive
form. This repetition is used for multiple reasons: to make the issues at stake
readily visible and hearable for everyone who is present, to possibly catch the
Defender in an error or a confusion, and to contribute to setting a rhythm or
pacing for their live dialectics. In this clip, the defenders confirm both
positive accounts and disconfirm the negative form of the account: … In order for the parties to promote the
result of their philosophical collaboration to the level of a social fact, not
only do they need to provide a public account and secure confirmation
for it, that account must be objectivated; that is, it must be turned
into a social object that is able to stand in front of the parties
independently of their talk. There are many practices that co-participants use
to achieve objectivation. The debaters here use a different practice for
objectivating the account than the ones found in our Game-with-Rules
illustration, but it accomplishes the same purpose. In this case the confirmed
account is objectivated by Defender 2’s assertion that “We say …,” which places
the facticity of the matter out of the hands of any of the individual actors, and
also by the Challenger’s rhythmical repetition of the account (which is much the
way an auctioneer will accomplish it). It becomes a fact-in-hand, from which the
parties will be able to proceed securely. This too conforms with our temporal model: Account → Confirmation → Objectivation With their “intersubjective thought object” (Schutz 1971: 12) in hand and “given equally to all” (Schutz 1967: 32), these Tibetan debaters can
proceed with a course of rigorous philosophical dialectics. 6.3 Espresso-Tasting Session The third illustration of the model is
extracted from a Coffee-Tasting Session in Italy guided by a master roaster, and
the parties are speaking Italian; an English translation is included with the
transcript. These lay tasters are offering their assessments of the flavors
they find in the espresso blends they are sampling. They are not doing blind
tasting, since these tasters collaborate about each flavor descriptor, and also
because their assessments are being subjected to review by the master roaster
who has designed blends of several coffees, and roasted and prepared them
according to a certain plan of his own. The parties still need to coordinate
what they will accept to be facts, which they do in the manner of our model, but
this is an occasion where claimed expertise does play a role in directing the
discussion: This illustration presents us with yet
another practice for objectivating an account. Although at first there was some
contestation on the part of C, the tasters confirm the appropriateness
of “dark chocolate” as a proper account for the taste, and that account
is expanded by the taste descriptor “peanuts.” The master roaster (C) combines
those two descriptors into the single descriptor “an oily seed,” and when his
summary account receives confirmation, C consolidates the authority of that
descriptor by objectivating it, which he accomplishes by giving it a universal
name (“the Italian extraction”) that suggests
widespread knowledge about it along with general acceptance of its veracity as
a definitive account. Following this, none of our tasters who wishes to appear
competent will contest that taste descriptor, and so it stands as a new fact of
life in the parties’ work of sensory evaluation. Although in each of our illustrations the parties employ
a different practice of objectivation, all three cases conform to the suggested
progressive sequence: Account → Confirmation → Objectivation Let me be clear about how I am treating this model:
these events surely do not take place just because I have developed a model.
And in the spirit of Garfinkel, I beg the reader not to pay too much attention
to it, for the reason that it can blind one to the radical events that are
going on and diminish the openness of any examination. Under no circumstances
should these stages be substituted for the concrete identification,
observation, and specification of the constituent activities. Even so, my
students in ethnomethodology have found this temporal description helpful for guiding
their inquiries regarding some of the more interesting aspects of ordinary
sociation. While much attention has been paid in the ethnomethodological literature
to accounts and to confirmation, less attention has been given to objectivation
practices, even though they are critical for the establishment of social facts.
The point of this exercise is to remedy this lacuna. In his studies of accounts and “formulations,”
Garfinkel observed that accounts require confirmation by others, and that any
formulation of local affairs was always “subject to review by others.” Accounts
are the corporate means by which candidate understandings become public objects.
Objectivating something, which means to construct a unity for it so that
it can be shared, retained, and communicated, is a topic that Edmund Husserl persisted
in examining from the period of Logical Investigations, in 1899, until
his final lectures in 1936, including “The Origin of Geometry.” In “The Origin
of Geometry,” Husserl (1970: 360) emphasized the importance of how concepts are
objectivated in the social world: “In the unity of communication among several
persons, the repeatedly produced structure becomes an object of consciousness,
not as a likeness, but as the one structure common to all.” For Alfred Schutz this objectivation
was key to his tracking of intersubjectivity, and he explained that it involves
the public work by which something is given equally to all. According to Schutz
(1971: 12) an intersubjective thought object is formulated by and for the
parties in order to facilitate the work of their sociality, and this was an
early clue for Garfinkel. For Schutz, who was the first to speak of production
in this way, the “objective meaning” refers to “the already constituted
meaning-context of the thing produced whose actual production we meanwhile
disregard” (Schutz 1967: 133-34). This “disregard” is the social amnesia, the
disengagement. One of Garfinkel’s discoveries was that parties are not
motivated by the meaning of an account as much as they are motivated by the
demand that they render their local affairs orderly. One way by which people learn just-what
they mean is to objectivate their notion and then observe what that
objectivated notion accomplishes, that is, just-what it comes to mean during
the course of their interaction. Once some understanding is discovered, that
is, as something begins to be played out in local affairs in a way that is
evident, that understanding can be displayed to everyone who is present,
and in that way an understanding can be made an objective fact that stands
independently of the people who staff the course of affairs. In the technical words
of Husserl, which were adopted and extended by Garfinkel, parties gradually
work to substitute “objective expressions” for “essentially subjective and
occasional expressions,” and this is work that is done collaboratively. Husserl did not investigate
extensively the local contingencies of this substitution, and Garfinkel (2002:
204-5) took that up as a principal topic for ethnomethodological research. In
undertaking these studies, Garfinkel and his students discovered something
fantastic: this local work can include situations where words, glosses, and
categories exist as objects for everyone before their practical
intelligibility is fixed. In fact, using the glosses in order to fix
their sense and reference is part of the work that a local cohort of actors
routinely performs when organizing the objective intelligibility of an
occasion. The part that is fascinating about this, and the part that is arational
about it (and here I do not mean non-rational, for the reason that rationality
can consist of precisely this), is that agreements can occur before people
understand just what they mean; but despite the blind into which a cohort is
willing to enter headfirst, from the outset the confirmed and objectivated account
is binding upon everyone, even before its sense and reference has been
fully determined. Let me specify this, using another example that involves lay
coffee tasters: “Bold” A It’s
definitely bold. B It’s
a very bold coffee. A I
definitely agree with the boldness … A It
was really sour, bitter, too strong. But bold. Interviewer:
What do you mean by “bold”? A He
was the one that said “bold.” How is bold? Here the first taster offers the original, albeit indeterminate
taste descriptor of “bold.” Possibly his immanent preoccupation was with
getting through the task without appearing dumb, but he did closely attend to
the coffee before offering his descriptor, a descriptor with which Taster B
agrees. Taster B’s agreement leads Taster A to double-down on his account. But
then the interviewer asks Taster A to explain to her just what this descriptor
means. At this, Taster A pretends that he was not the one who proposed the
descriptor. His gambit makes it evident that he did not possess a clear
understanding of the meaning of his descriptor. Since probably Taster B also lacked
a clear understanding about just what was intended by the account he was
confirming, when the two tasters consolidated their affirmation of the
descriptor, they were validating an account that lacked specific content. In my
coffee-tasting data, specification of such content is a matter that is sometimes
left to subsequent tasting and discussion. In this case the Interviewer’s
question exposes the vacuity of the tasters’ formulation of the coffee’s flavor.
In Taster A’s defense it should be observed that according to the way that
social facts are produced, and to how accounts are objectivated, the propriety
of an account is very much the result of a collaboration among the parties, and
so it might be said that Taster B had as much to do with the objectivation of
the account as did Taster A. What is vital for the success of the interaction
is that the parties provide some order to their assessment and are able to operate
on the same page. Their adoption of an account before it acquired its content
was how they accomplished that. Here is another instance of persons
who agree with a formulation before they know what it means. It comes from my
data on games-with-rules: "Okay" Bill:
[Reading rules] “You may trade resources with other players for using
maritime trade.” Linda: Okay. Bill: Which we don’t know what
that is. Linda: ’Kay. Bill:
[Summarizing rules] You may build roads, settlements, or cities. And/or buy
development cards. You may also play one development card any time during your
turn. After you’re done, pass the dice to your left, who then continues the
game by repeating what we just did. Linda: So
I can like roll and get settlement cards or I mean like resource cards and then
I can like do stuff? Bill: Yep. In the case of this interaction, which
depicts gameplayers collaborating in the task of working out what the rules for
gameplay are supposed to mean, we know that they have agreed upon a gloss for
some gameplay without knowing what they have agreed to because one of the
parties observes publicly, “We don’t know what that is.” This does not deter the parties from
continuing to review the rules in such a manner. It is common for parties to
read rules that are not intelligible; in fact, when the reading is divorced
from some gameplay, rules frequently are not intelligible, and so it is rare
for gameplayers to read all the rules of a game before they commence play. Too
much reading of unintelligible material can render a local social interaction
absurd. For this reason, Linda offers her gratuitous cooperation, and that is
not an unimportant step in allowing the parties to proceed with organizing
their understanding, but that understanding lies ahead of them in the
interaction and so is part of what Schutz and Garfinkel have called the
prospective and retrospective sense of understanding, which has played an
important role in ethnomethodological analyses. Bill’s “Yep” in the final line
of the transcript is probably gratuitous as well. John Heritage and Geoffrey
Raymond (2005: 15) suggest, “Within the general framework of agreement on a
state of affairs, the matter of the terms of agreement can remain,” and
Heritage (2013: 383) tells us, “In the midst of agreeing with one another,
speakers are still addressing the terms of agreement.” Heritage and
Raymond emphasize there can be a “raw affiliation” (2005: 17) that lacks any content
and amounts to merely “a simulacrum of agreement.” These raw affiliations are
fascinating and deserve further study because they help to reveal the brute
sociality of our lives. Even though an agreement lacks
content and does not yet mean very much, that the local cohort has already
accepted an account serves to assist the account in winning the moral authority
of a social fact in the way that Durkheim has elaborated. In fact, all three
stages of our model can be fulfilled without there being much content behind
the material expression of an account. A good deal of what makes conversations
interesting, even exciting, is that the meaning of an interaction is often left
unresolved, presenting participants with the highly engaging task of resolving
matters, at least for practical purposes. Here I am not at all speaking about
how individual understandings get “negotiated.” More commonly, no one knows
what is going on, and parties discover only serendipitously, inside-with the
emerging affairs, some way to get on the same page. And it does not necessarily
have to really be the same page, it can be that the parties only think it is
the same page. Situations like that are hardly rare. It is possible to become
capable of better recognizing them when we abandon our practice of believing
our own social mythologizing; however, there are practical benefits in
organizing the local orderliness of some social interaction by working out a structure
and using it to coordinate the interaction before the participants themselves
have recognized the meaning and consequences of what they have accomplished. In
fact, it is difficult to imagine social life without this. 7.1 Anonymity and moral compliance The immortality of social facts was an orientation Durkheim
developed by considering Montaigne, who spoke of the mystical authority of the
law. What are the origins of this “mystical authority”? To some extent it must be
rooted in a sense of responsibility for others’ expectations; but why is there
a sense of responsibility for other’s expectations? Here we discover a second
sense of “accountability.” The first sense of accountability is how the intelligibility
of emerging affairs can be summarized in an account, as I have been describing,
and the second sense of the term is how we can be oriented to the expectations
of others and so are “accountable” to others for affirmation of the
appropriateness of our behavior. Commonly, others’ expectation is that we will be
cooperative, and this is an expectation that can be easily read on the face of the
other. Moreover, in many circumstances our very first objective is to stay out
of trouble and we are eager to be cooperative, even though we may not yet know
what it is we need to do in order to be cooperative. Garfinkel (1967: 35) begins his
“Studies of the Routine Grounds of Everyday Activities” – which remains the
name for our “studies” even today – by discussing Kant, for whom there were two
“mysteries,” the stars in the heavens and the moral order within: “For Kant the
moral order ‘within’ was an awesome mystery; for sociologists the moral order
‘without’ is a technical mystery.” Here we are examining this moral order “without,”
and the responsibility about which I am speaking is anonymous. That is
to say, it is any member’s practice. Let’s have a closer look at it. "Devo dire?" A Here Italian lay tasters are doing their
best to comply with the protocols of proper coffee-tasting, but they are
handicapped by the fact that they do not really know what those protocols are.
They were given a form on which to note some taste descriptors and to offer a
few numerical evaluations of some categories of flavor. Taster A commences her
summary by reading off her sheet: A Allora, io he escrito, va ben,
amaro. E noce especiato, ho cerchiato, però poi ho scritto “poco corposo.” Here she pauses in order to read how her contribution
is being received by the others, and she pays particular attention to the young
bearded man at the end of the table who is facing her (see clip) and who is the
organizer for the tasting session. Gazes like this are opportunities for
parties to solicit what their account has come to mean and also for
monitoring their satisfactory compliance with what is expected. In this way her
gaze services both senses of the term “account.” She hesitates here because she
is uncertain about just what she is supposed to do next. So she asks of the
session organizer, “Am I supposed to say the numbers too?”: "Devo dire?" B A Devo dire anche i
numeretti? B Si, se vuoi si. A Va ben. Aroma 6,
corposità 3, equilibrio 5, dolcezza 5, vellutato 3, e retrogusto 7. What is noteworthy about this this clip is that B, the organizer of the
session, does not really have a preference regarding how A reports her sensory
evaluation. In fact, he is deferring to her even as she is deferring to him (note
particularly B’s facial gestures at second 0.04 in the “Devo dire?” B
Clip). Such an “After you, Alphonse” / “No, after you” routine is a comedy that
is common in our interactional affairs. Taster A is ready and willing to comply
with any rules that are in force; her problem is that she does not yet know what
those rules are. In this clip the situation is even worse than this, since no
rules have been established. The openness of the structure for interacting can sometimes
become paralyzing, so A proceeds with one way to accomplish her reporting,
which, by the time the other tasters take their turns, becomes the authorized
way to do it, presenting us with one more case of an event organizing itself. What
is occurring is that each participant is attempting to locate a local structure,
and the parties’ desire in general for a structure, any structure, is more
important than the particular structure that they adopt. Such a situation is responsible
for many follies in our everyday lives. For instance, a first person can
suggest an account, and that account can elicit a confirmation by a second
person; however, it can (and does) happen that a second person misunderstands
the meaning of the account given by the first person and so confirms something that
the first person did not intend. It can also happen that the first person will
decide not to correct the second person, even when the first person recognizes
that the account has been misunderstood (cf. Liberman 2017: 171-215). How can
this happen? One way it can happen is that a third person, who does not
understand the sense or reference of the account but who does recognize that
the first person and the second person are in agreement about it, will nod his
or her head and confirm the account gratuitously. It could be that the first
person may have been ready to correct the second person until the third person
offers the additional gratuitous confirmation. The additional confirmation can
cause the first person to choose to remain silent, first because the immanent
local work of undoing a confirmed or objectivated structure can become a
complicated matter, and second because it appears that a satisfactory communal
agreement has been reached and there may be some reluctance to disrupt an
established harmony, even when the harmony is only apparent. It is possible
that the first person thinks that the second and third persons understand what
they have agreed about. All of the parties (including a fourth party who
remains silent, and confused) can even act on the basis of an account confirmed
this way. For the sake of giving some flesh to our example, let us say that the
topic was about the group going to a movie, and the first person suggests a
currently playing movie that stars Denzel Washington, who is presently starring
in two movies; the second person thinks only of the current movie that was not the
one that the first person had intended. In the way described, the four of them can
head off to watch a movie that none of them had a desire to see. Moreover,
that no one wanted to see the movie can remain opaque to each of the parties.
There is no way that social scientists could gauge how many decisions are set
into motion in just such a fashion, so intricate is the interaction. What I am
describing is ubiquitous, and it can involve a matter as simple as when parties
laugh together heartily without knowing what it is they are laughing about. The responsibility that people
feel to comply with others’ expectations operates in the midst of the
objectivation practices. In
the transition from the article, “Studies of the Routine Grounds of Everyday
Activities” that appeared in Social Problems in 1964, to the second chapter
by the same name of his 1967 Studies in Ethnomethodology, Garfinkel
omitted the first paragraph of his “Concluding Remarks,” which read, “The
expectancies that make up the attitude of everyday life are constitutive of the
institutionalized common understandings of the practical everyday
organization…” (Garfinkel 1964: 249). Part of the motive for objectivating accounts or institutionalizing
common understandings is that any compliance with what is expected needs to be
organized, and what behavior it is that can constitute correct compliance must
be something that everyone present is able to recognize, since this knowledge
must become a public possession. Moreover, when people act in compliance they do
not act as individual actors but as sort of a local “anyone,” as an anonymous
“member.” Accordingly, part of the local work of parties is to provide for the public
recognizability of the methods and agreements that are set into play. The work
of making them recognizable (that is, “instructably observable and instructably
reproducible” (Garfinkel 2002: 148)) is collective, and such work is not
usually undertaken on one’s personal behalf but is done anonymously. I have observed that each party
is preoccupied with figuring out what must be done “next” before the time to do
it arrives. Since events can move very fast (there are no “timeouts”), strange
things can happen. These strange things can become an embarrassment for social
scientists who take their “Just So Stories” seriously. My argument here is that
we need to abandon some of the social mythologies of rules,
laws, negotiated agreements, etc., which render our lives more deliberate
and rational than they in fact are,[7]
and pay closer attention to the granular details of social interaction
turn-by-turn and move-by-move. Let us learn from the real world of which we
speak. Surely this aspiration is a
component of what comprises the study of “sociality” that Simmel recommended. Simmel
(1959: 328) writes, “Perhaps this sort of insight will do for social science
what the beginnings of microscopy did for the science of organic life.” I
certainly hope so. Indeed, the fine-grained, turn-by-turn analyses of
ethnomethodology involve just this kind of microscopy. Attewell, P. (1974)
“Ethnomethodology Since Garfinkel.” In Theory and Society 1: 179-210. Daston, Lorraine, and Peter
Galison 2010 Objectivity. NY: Zone Books. Cicourel, A. (1974) Cognitive Sociology: Language and Meaning
in Social Interaction Garfinkel, H. (1964) “Studies of the Routine Grounds of Everyday Activities.” In Social Problems 11:
225-250. Garfinkel, H. (1967)
Studies in Ethnomethodology. Englewood Cliffs, MJ: Prentice-Hall. Garfinkel, H. (1974)
Soc 149 Class Lectures given at UCLA’s Department of Sociology. Garfinkel, H. (2006)
Seeing Sociologically: The Routine Grounds of Social Action. Boulder,
Colorado: Paradigm Publishers. Gurwitsch,
A.
(1966)
Studies in Phenomenology and Psychology, Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern
University Press. Heidegger, M. (1962)
Being and Time. Trans. by John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson. NY:
Harper & Row. Heritage, J. &
Raymond, G. (2005)
“The Terms of Agreement: Epistemic Authority and Subordination in
Talk-in-Interaction.” In Social Psychology Quarterly 68 (1):15-38. Heritage, J. (2013)
“Epistemics in Conversation.” In The Handbook of Conversation Analysis,
eds. Jack Sidnell and Tanya Stivers. Oxford: Blackwell. Husserl,
E.
(1962)
Ideas: General Introduction to Pure Phenomenology. London:
Collier-Macmillan. Husserl, E.
(1969)
Formal and Transcendental Logic. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff. Husserl, E.
(1970)
“The Origin of Geometry,” Appendix I in Edmund Husserl, The Crisis of the
European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology. Evanston, Ill.:
Northwestern University Press. Husserl,
E.
(1973)
Experience and Judgment. Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press. Liberman,
K. (2004)
Dialectical Practice in
Tibetan Philosophical Culture. Lanham, Md.: Rowman & Littlefield. Liberman,
K. (2013)
More Studies in
Ethnomethodology. Albany, NY: SUNY Press. Liberman,
K. (2017) Understanding Interaction in
Central Australia: An Ethnomethodological Study of Australian Aboriginal People Macbeth,
D. (2011)
“Understanding Understanding as an Instructional Matter. Journal of
Pragmatics43 (2): 438-451.
Merleau-Ponty, M. (1962)
Phenomenology of Perception. London: Routledge. Moerman,
M. & Sacks, H. (1988)
“On ‘Understanding’ in the Analysis of Natural Conversation.” In Moerman, Talking
Culture, Ethnography and Conversation Analysis. Philadelphia: University of
Pennsylvania Press, pp. 180-86. Proust, M. (2002)
Finding Time Again. London: Penguin
Books. Psathas, G. (2004)
“The Correspondence of Alfred Schutz and Harold Garfinkel.” In H. Nasu, L. Embree, G. Psathas and I. Srubar (eds.), Alfred
Schutz and His Intellectual Partners. Konstanz: UVK Verlagsgesselschaft
mbH, pp. 401-434. Schutz,
A.
(1967)
Phenomenology of the Social World. Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern
University Press. Schutz,
A.
(1971)
Collected Papers, Vol. I. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff. Simmel, G. (1959a)
“The Problem of Sociology,” in Essays on Sociology, Philosophy and
Aesthetics. NY: Harper & Row, pp. 310-36. Simmel, G. (1959a)
“How Is Society Possible?” in Essays on Sociology, Philosophy and Aesthetics.
NY: Harper & Row, pp. 337-56. [1] This paper is
based upon a plenary address delivered at the 12th Conference of the
International Institute for Ethnomethodology and Conversation Analysis
(IIEMCA), held at the University of Southern Denmark in August of 2015. Two
earlier and primitive versions of that address were given, one in 2014 as the
keynote at the Annual
‘BrainFood’ Conference, University of Southern Denmark, Odense, Denmark, under
the title “Some Arational Bases of Rational Activities;” and the other as a talk in 2015 to the Facoltà di
Sociologia at the Università di Trento and published in their departmental
papers (“Studying
Objectivation Practices,” in Quaderni del Dipartimento di Sociologia e Ricerca Sociale, Università di Trento,
Italy, New Series (Electronic), No. 2, 2016, pp. 1-22). [2] By major or macro social
forms Simmel (1959: 326-27) is referring to “superindividual
structures”: “Great organs and systems like states, labor unions, priesthoods,
family forms, economic systems, military organizations, guilds, communities,
class formations, and industrial divisions of labor, seem to constitute society
and therefore appear to be the subject matter of the science of society.” [3] “The Boston Seminar,” 6/24/75. This is available
online at the EMCA-Legacy website (http://emca-legacy.info/garfinkel.html). [4] Chapter 5 of Ethnomethodology’s
Program (Garfinkel 2002: 169-93) is as good a place to begin as any other. [5] An initial
explanation, along with a case study, is available in Liberman 2004: 92-106. [6] The fourth
component, Disengagement, awaits fuller specification. [7] For a brief
expansion of this ethnomethodological perspective on rules, visit “Le Regole di
Surf: Intervista a Kenneth Liberman SurfinSalento.it,” available at times
31:34-35:00 (the only portion of the interview that is in English) on the video
that is available at https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=WpOjNm4AbTw&feature=youtu.be
OK.
… “Velvet texture”? …
4. Excursus: Some historical perspective
5. Congregational work
6. Objectivation
D:
What do we do if the die rolls on the floor?
B:
Well if it’s offensive.
D:
/Re- //Re-roll
-Account
B:
/ // Re-roll.
-Confirmation
C:
Hah.-
A:
House rule of Aggravation.
-Objectivation
C:
[Laughs while gazing at D.]
Challenger
The reflection of a face in the mirror in the continuum of
an ordinary person is posited by the mind as erroneous.
-Account
Defender-1:
It is. It is.
-Confirmation
Challenger:
It does not follow that the lack of accord between the
appearance of the reflection of the face in the mirror and its mode of being is posited. [Hand-clap]
9:04:53
-Negative-of-
-Account
Defender-2:
CHEE-CHEER [lit. “Because of what?” = No]
-Disconfirmation
Challenger:
So, the lack of accord between the appearance of
the reflection of the face in the mirror and its mode of being is posited. [Hand-clap]
9:04:55
-Repeat-of-
-Account
Defender-2:
Yes.
-Confirmation
Challenger:
It follows that the mind that has posited
the lack of accord between the appearance of
the reflection of the face in the mirror and
its mode of being is not complete, according to the Middle Way. [Hand-clap]
9:04:59
-Extension of
-Account
Defender-2:
We say it is not complete.
-Objectivation
A
Cioccolato /fondente
Dark chocolate
-Account
B
/Cioccolato
Chocolate
-Confirmation
C
Mm.
D
Molto leggero come cioccolato fondente.
Very light-tasting, like dark chocolate.Sarcasm:
-Disconfirmation
C
No, anche perchè ho detto il cioccolato.
No, because I also said chocolate.
-Re-Confirmation
D
Positivo o negativo, non lo so.
Positive or negative, I don’t know.
E
Positivo positivo.
Positive positive.
C
Positivo.
Positive.
B
[Bevande]
[Drinks]
E
A me ricorda un’arach-l’arachido. Il sapore dell’ arachido.
For me it recalls pea-peanuts. The flavor of peanuts.
-Extension of
C
Quindi sempre un seme olioso.
Therefore always an oily seed.
-Summary Account
E
Si! Proprio quel sapore.
Yes! That’s the very flavor here.
-Confirmation
C
Allora, quest’olio qui è tipico del, dell’estrazione all’italiana.
So then, this oil here is typical of, of “the Italian extraction.”
-Objectivation
7. Discussion
So, I have
written, all right, bitter. And walnut spice, I circled,
but then I
wrote “little body.”
Am I supposed
to say the numbers too?
Yes, if you want
to, sure.
All right. Aroma 6, body 3, balance 5, sweetness 5,
velvet 3, and aftertaste 7.
References