Nationaløkonomisk Tidsskrift, Bind 130 (1992) Festskrift til Sven Danø og R Nørregaard Rasmussen (II)Savage's Independence Axiom and the Von Neumann-Morgenstern Substitution AxiomInstitute of Economics, University of Copenhagen Anders Borglin ResuméSUMMARY: We consider the relation between a Savage-agent, an agent in the sense of Savage (1954), and a v. N-M-agent, an agent in the sense of von Neumann and Morgenstern It is shown that, if the Savage-agent is consistent with the v.N-Magent, the sense that his preferences among random variables agree with the v.N-Magent's among the corresponding distributions, then the v.N-M.agent satisfies Substitution axiom on a subset if and only if the Savage-agent satisfies the Independence axiom on a corresponding subset and certain induced agents, called relatives of the Savage-agent, are also consistent with the same v.N-M.agent. 1. IntroductionIn the theory of choice under uncertainty there are two main approaches, one initiated Savage (1954), and the other one initiated by von Neumann-Morgenstern (1944). We will discuss the relationship between an important axiom in Savage's theory, Independence axiom, and an equally inportant axiom in von Neumann-Morgensterns' the Substitution axiom.1 We will show that a Savage-agent, an agent in the sense of Savage, satisfies the Independence axiom "to the same extent" that the corresponding v.N-M.-agent, an agent in the sense of von Neumann-Morgenstern, satisfies the Substitution axiom. It turns out that, in order to do so, we have to assume, not only that the Savage-agent himself, but also that certain derived agents, called relatives the given Savage-agent, are consistent with the corresponding v.N-M-agent. Savage's approach to the theory of choice under uncertainty, is closely related to the theory of consumer choice, under uncertainty in the theory of general equilibrium. In that theory, there are no external probabilities and an agent's preferences depict his attitudes the outcomes (prizes, consequences) as well as his, subjective, probability 1. This axiom is also referred to as "the Independence Axiom" or "the Cancellation Axiom". We prefer to use "the Substitution Axiom" to avoid misunderstandings. Side 268
In the von
Neumann-Morgenstern theory, which was developed along
with their Uncertainty arises in Savage's theory because Nature chooses among "states of the World". Once the agent has chosen an act (random variable) Nature's choice determines prize (consequence, outcome) the agent will actually receive. Thus, if S is the set of "states of the world", X is the set of prizes, the objects of choice are the functions from S to X, that is, random variables ? These will typically be denoted by £ 17 and the set of random variables is S(S, X). The agent is assumed to have a preference son the set of random variables, which is a total preorder. The Independence
axiom is concerned with two pairs. £, 17 and £' 17', of
such random the restriction to A of £ and £'are equal the restriction to A of 77 and 17' are equal the restriction to S \ A of £ and 17 are equal the restriction to S\Aof£' and 17' are equal Then according to the Independence axiom: £ sl7if and only if £' s 17'. The rationale for the axiom is as follows. If Nature chooses s in S \A then £ and 17 give the agent the same price. Hence the agent must base his evalution of £ and 17 on the prizes he will receive if nature chooses s in A. But £ and 17 are equal to £' an 17' respectively, on A, and £' is equal to 17' on S \A. Thus the evaluation of £' and 17' should be based on the prized received, if Nature chooses 5 in A. But then £' and 17' should be ordered in the same way as £ and 17. The von
Neumann-Morgenstern theory takes the probability
measures on X, to be 2. In this section no mention will be made of the necessary measurability conditions. A function defined on a measurable space with values in a measurable space, is a random variable also if there is no probability defined on the domain. 3. Often the Substitution Axiom is formulated with an "only if". Cf. Kreps (1988). Side 269
This axiom is often motivated by considering two compound lotteries. (Cf. Duffie (1988) or Kreps (1988). The first one gives the distribution tt' as a prize, with probability and the distribution tt, with probability (\ -a). The second one gives tt", with probability a, and tt with probability (I -a). Since, in both lotteries, tt is received with probability (I - a), the preferences concerning the other prizes ought, according to the axiom, to determine the preferences among the two compound lotteries. In Savage's theory the Independence axiom, together with the other axioms, determine probability measure on S, reflecting the subjective probability judgements of the agent. Here we will assume that such a measure, P, is given. For a random variable, £ S -» X, the distribution of £ is then given by P (£''( •)), assigning to each event (measurable of X) the probability of the event. With the
probability measure P given, it makes sense to inquire
if a Savage-agent, this we mean: £
£s t? if and only if P(^1 (¦)) S: P(j)A(')). Assume that [3(S,
X), SJ is consistent with [11, The idea that there
should be Let tt', tt", it
E II and let 0 < a < 1. Let n = air' + (1 - a) tt
and 71 = oltt" + Then (U, €s\a).
defined by (U, £s\a) (s) =€a (s) for sGA, and (£A',
£SXA)(s) = (*) Assume that tt'
tt" and that the Substitution axiom is satisfied. By
(*), (^Af, £s\a) Side 270
may define on S (A, X) by: U $a" if and only if féj. £su^s (W, £s\a) for some €s\a- (*) men als° implies that gA A £A". Hence the Substitution axiom implies that the preferences A induced by s, on restrictions of functions in E (S, X) also agree with On the other hand, if the Independence axiom is satisfied then n 5: n and we would have the Substitution axiom satisfied if tt' tt". This will be the case if %A A £,A implies tt' tt" , that is, if the Savage-agent [E (A, X), is also consistent with fa *]. We call a derived agent, like [E (A, X), <zA], a relative of [E (S, X), SJ. The considerations suggests that if a Savage-agent is consistent with a v.N-M-agent then the v.N-M-agent satisfies the Substitution axiom if and only if the Savage-agent and his relatives are consistent with the v.N-M-agent. In the sequel we will show that a general version, using restricted versions of the Substitution axiom and the Independence axiom, of this is actually true. Before proceeding
we note the following difficulties: (1) If ft is
"large", it may be difficult to find a set of "states of
the world", S, and a (2) There seems
to be nothing to ensure that (^A, £S\a)~s €a">€s\a)
f°r every £S\a: (3) The
distributions of £A and/or £A" may not belong to the set
of distributions generated 2. NotationFor easy
reference we list the notation to be used in the sequel.
&nA={BIB
=C(IA,C£ &}. AeftP: probability measure on Sf.
£, 17 '•
measureable functions from S to X. E(A, X): the
set of measureable functions defined on A with values in
X, A G SP\ /(()/. 4. Topological conditions on X, ensuring that there is an underlying set of "states of the world", 5, and a (single) probability measure, P on 5, generating the probability measures on X, as the distributions induced by random variables from 5 to X, can be found in Hildenbrand (1974) and the references given there. Side 271
A:
preferences on E (A, X),A G Sf\ {§}, induced by s
II: a
non-empty subset of TI(X). iTg, iTyj
distributions of £, rj G E(A, X). 7TgA, 7rVA
distributions of gA, r\A G E(A, X),A G
&>,&>, P(A) >0 (induced by the
probability Let A, BG £f, A, B disjoint and non-empty, and let gA: A—> X, £B :B—» Xbe respectively n and 5^ (1 5-measureable functions. Then (%A, £&) denotes & n (A U s^-measureable, function from A U B to to be £A(s), for s GA, and £flfo), for sGB. gA, A G £f\ {<{)}, will also be used to denote the restriction to A, of a function £GE(S,X). 3. Savage AgentsDefinition: A
Savage-agent is a pair. [E(A, X), where A G sf\
{((>}, E(A, X) is The reason we want to allow for preferences, which are not total preorders is that, given the Savage-agent, [E(S, X), we will define agents induced by the Savageagent, may have preferences, that are not total preorders. These induced agents will be the relatives of the Savage-agent. Define a set sd,
which is to be fixed in the sequel, by Definition: Let
SB be a subset of si. A Savage-agent [jz (S, X),
satisfies Savage- Savage's
Independence axiom corresponds to the case SB = si.
Side 272
Definition: Let a
Savage-agent [S (S, X), satisfy Savage-Independence on a
a £A" if and only
if (A, (£A\ £,". £5X JE® for some £S,A eE (A, X) and
The preference
relation &A depends on the set 38. If the set 38 is
small the relation Definition: Let a
Savage-agent [E (S, X), satisfy Savage-Independence on
subset The concepts above
are defined without any reference to the probability
measure on 4. v.N-M-AgentsDefinition: A
v.N-M-agent is a pair. [H&J where FI is a subset of
IJ(X) and is a Define a set %
which is to be fixed in the sequel, by Definition: Let
2) be a subset of c€. A v.N-M-agent, [Tl,^], satisfies
the Substitution The next definition captures the notion of a Savage-agent, or a relative, who ranks random variables taking into account only their distributions. To make sense we assume the probability measures used are P, on (S, &), and p^ P(-), on (A, tf (1 A), for A E 5^ such that P(A) > 0. A relative is non-trivial if P(A) > 0. Definition: A
non-trivial 58-relative of a Savage-agent, [E (A, X),
S:J, of a Savageagent, Side 273
If a relative of a Savage-agent is consistent with a v.N-M-agent and Aisa total preorder, then TI(A, X) C TI, but the inclusion might be proper. The relation A may be very incomplete, but if Aisa total preorder, then the final line in the definition is equivalent to: 5. ResultUsing the
definitions introduced we can now state the following
result, the proof of Theorem. Let the
Savage-agent [S (S, X), S:s] be consistent with the
v.N-M-agent Then
The
Savage-agent satisfies Savage-Independence on Sft and
all the non-trivial 38relatives if and only
if [11,
satisfies the Substitution-axiom on 2). Proof: "Only if"
If is empty then Q) is empty and we are finished. Let
(a, it', Since (A,tjAf,
t;A" {jS\a) & ar|d [Z (S, X), s-J satisfies
Savage-Independence on We now have
Side 274
where (1) is true since
[E (A, X), A] is consistent with [11, (2) is true since
[E (S, X), s] satisfies Savage-Independence on 58.
"If". Let
[11, satisfy the Substitution axiom on 2. Let (A.tjJ,
£A", £SKA) E$ and If P(A) S {o,l}
the conclusion follows from the assumption that [E (S,
X), is Assume 0< P(A)
< 1. By the definition of % there are (a, it', ir",
tt), We get where (1) is true since
[E (S, X), is consistent with [11, (2) by the
definition of the distributions of (€A\ £SS\A) and (gA",
S\a) Let [E (A, X),
<^/ be a 38-relative of [E (S, X), Sr^/. Then, since
[E (S, X), is Side 275
and a similar
argument shows that gj >A g^' implies ir^ > tt^ ».
6. ConclusionsWe have shown that if a Savage-agent is consistent with a v.N-M-agent then the Savage-agent satisfies Savage-Independence and his non-trivial relatives are consistent with the same v.N-M-agent if and only if the v.N-M-agent satisfies the Substitution axiom. If one considers the Independence axiom as intuitively more appealing than the Substitution axiom, the latter could thus be derived from the former. However, in doing so one is forced to make assumptions regarding, not only the Savage-agent, but also his relatives. The analysis points to two problems: One is to give an example of a Savage-agent who is consistent with a v.N-M-agent, but who has a non-trivial relative who is not consistent the same v.N-M-agent. A second one is to state conditions, under which the consistency of the Savage-agent himself implies that his relatives are also consistent. ReferencesDuffie, D. 1988.
Security Markets, Stochastic Hildenbrand, W.
1974. Core and Equilibria of Kreps, D. M.
1988. Notes on the Theory of Von Neumann, J.
and Morgenstern, O. 1944. Savage, L. J.
1954. The Foundation of Statistics. |