Nationaløkonomisk Tidsskrift, Bind 130 (1992) Festskrift til Sven Danø og R Nørregaard Rasmussen (I)

Existence of Equilibrium in CAPM Further Results

Institute of Economics, University of Copenhagen

Lars Tyge Nielsen

Resumé

SUMMARY In the mean-variance capital asset pricing model (CAPM), non-monotonicity preferences may lead to satiation and non-existence of equilibrium if there is no riskless asset. This paper generalizes one of the earlier existence results for general equilibrium. Among other things, the restrictive assumption that utility be concave in mean and variance is dispensed with. In addition, it is observed that there virtually always an equality-constrained general equilibrium, where investors maximize subject to an equality budget constraint.

1. Introduction

In the two-period mean-variance capital asset pricing model (CAPM), a general equilibrium may fail to exist because of non-monotonicity of preferences and satiation as well as because of the possibility of short-selling. This paper provides some new existence results.

Nielsen (1989) exhibited sufficient conditions for existence of a general equilibrium in a model which allowed for satiation but was somewhat more general than the CAPM. These conditions were applied to the CAPM without a riskless asset in Nielsen (1990b). The conclusion was, essentially, that a general equilibrium exists if the investors on the expected returns to all assets, and if their risk aversion at a particular satisfies a certain inequality. The inequality ensures that satiation occurs only outside the relevant range of portfolios or combinations of standard deviation and mean. Nielsen (1992) derived a number of conditions that ensure positivity of equilibrium

Nielsen (1990a) derived complete necessary and sufficient conditions for existence of a general equilibrium in two special situations: one where utility is linear in mean and variance, and the other where the market portfolio minimizes the ratio of mean to standard deviation of return. Homogeneous beliefs were assumed.

For the case where there is a riskless asset, Nielsen (1990b) showed that there exists
a general equilibrium if the investors either agree on all expected returns or have sufficiently
limiting risk aversion.

Side 190

Using a quite different technique, Allingham (1991) has derived an alternative existence for a general equilibrium with positive prices in the CAPM without a riskless and with homogeneous beliefs. It assumes two vector inequalities for each investor, involving the parameters of the model and the measure of risk aversion. Instead the standard assumption that utility is concave or quasi-concave in mean and standard deviation, it relies on the more restrictive assumption that utility is concave in mean and variance.

The present paper derives an existence theorem which generalizes Allingham's result. assumes a single numerical inequality for each investor, and it depenses with the assumption that utility is concave in mean and variance. The theorem does not in general positivity of prices.

However in the special case that corresponds to Allingham's result, positive prices
are indeed guaranteed.

We show that the inequalities involved do not need to hold globally, but only in a relevant of portfolios, specifically at all individually rational allocations. That is significantly weaker than the global requirement, because the set of individually rational is compact (under the assumption of homogeneous beliefs, which is maintained in this part of the analysis).

Mainly as a technical device we introduce the concept of equality-constrained general They are almost the same thing as general equilibria, except that the investors maximize utility subject to an equality budget constraint instead of an inequality. nice thing about equality-constrained general equlibria is that they virtually always exist. The method of proof in our main general equilibrium existence result is to pick an equality-constrained general equilibrium and show that it is, in fact, a general equilibrium. There is, however, something to be said for equality-constrained general equilibrium concept in its own right. If the mean-variance model is interpreted as a model of a market for contracts that may turn out to be liabilities, then one may argue that the individual investor cannot freely dispose of a part of his endowment. He must choose to hold a portfolio which is equal in value to his endowment, and so he optimizes to an equality budget constraint.

We show the existence of equality-constrained general equilibrium in a model which is somewhat more general than the mean-variance model. In fact, we show something slightly stronger. There exists what we call a modified general equilibrium, where all satiable investors maximize subject to an equality constraint, while the insatiable investors subject to an inequality constraint.

The paper is based in part on Nielsen (1985).

The plan of the paper is this. Section 3 proves the existence of modified general
equilibria and equality-constrained general equilibria in a generalized model. Section 2

Side 191

applies the results of Section 3 to the CAPM and then uses them to prove the main
existence result for general equilibria.

2. Equilibrium in CAPM

This section explores the conditions for existence of equilibrium in the two-period mean-variance CAPM. First, we derive the conditions for existence of an equality-constrained equilibrium. The results of that analysis are then used to prove our main existence result for general equilibrium.

There are n assets. & portfolio is represented by an «-vectorx, where they'th entry
indicates the number of shares of they'th asset included in the portfolio. Short-selling
is allowed, so that the number Xj of shares of asset7 held in a portfolio may be negative.

There are m investors / = \,...,m. All investors have choice set IR", which means that there are no short sales constraints. Each summarizes his beliefs about the total (gross) returns per share of the assets in a mean vector R' and a covariance matrix 17,. These may, in general, differ across investors. The mean return to a portfolio x according to i's beliefs is x'R1, and the standard deviation is at(x) = (x'fljx)1'2. At times, it will be assumed that the investors agree on the expected returns or the variances and covariances, which case we write R' = R, 17, = 17, and a( (x) = o~(x).

A portfolio x is riskless (as judged by investor /) if crfx) = 0. It will be assumed that either there is no riskless asset or else the first asset is riskless while the remaining assets are risky. More specifically, in the first case (no riskless asset), it is assumed that the full covariance matrices 17, are positive definite. In the second case (where the first asset is riskless), the total return to the first (riskless) asset is assumed to be positive, and the covariance matrices of returns to the remaining assets are assumed to be positive These assumptions imply that there are no redundant assets or portfolios: All portfolios e^O have (afe), e' Rl)Rl) (0,0) for all i.

Investor / has utility function Wj(v,fx) which is a function of the variance and mean
of total portfolio return. It is defined for v > 0 and for values of \x. The corresponding
utility function for standard deviation and mean is Uj(a, /jl) = W^o2, /x).

Assumption 1. W-, is continuously differentiable (also at v =0) with W'iv <0 and W,'^
> 0, and Uj is quasi-concave.

The investor's utility function for portfolios is


DIVL3846

It is continuous and strongly quasi-concave. By definition, the latter means that
Vftx + (\-t)y) > Vj(y) whenever x andy are portfolios with Vt(x) > V,(y).

As discussed in Nielsen (1987), Vt may not be monotone, and it may exhibit satiation
there is no riskless asset.

Side 192

An allocation is an w-tuple (x') = (x\..., xm ) consisting of a portfolio jc, for each /. The investors are endowed with an initial portfolio allocation (co'). The market portfolio = Z,o>' indicates the total number of shares available of each asset. An attainable allocation is an allocation (x') such that £, x' = co.

A general equilibrium is a pair (p, (x')), where/? oisa price system (an and (xl) is an attainable allocation, such that for each /, p'x' <p 'co', and if y' is a portfolio p'y' <, then V'(y') <¦ Vj(x'). The initial allocation (co') is exogenously given, while the asset price vector p and the equilibrium portfolio allocation (x1) are endogenous.

The possibility of satiation and the unboundedness of the investors' choice sets may lead to non-existence of a general equilibrium in this model, cf. Nielsen (1990a). One possible way to deal with this problem is to consider equality-constrained general equilibria

An equality-constrained general equilibrium is a price vector p ¥" 0 and an attainable (x1) such that for each investor /, x' is optimal for /ifhe has wealth w' = p 'co' and his budget constraint is an equality. In other words, p'x' = p 'co', and if v' is a portfolio in X* with V, (yj) >V, (xl), then p'/ p 'x'.

The wealth of investor / is w' =p 'col, and now his budget constraint says p 'x' = w' rather than p'x' < w' . In ordinary consumption theory, one idea behind the inequality budget constraint p 'x' < w' is that there is a numeraire good which does not affect preferences. The consumer first exchanges his endowment for units of the numeraire and then uses some or all of the numeraire to purchase ordinary goods (or assets). If the numeraire has a positive value, then the budget constraint is an inequality when the value of the amount of the numeraire retained is not included in the value of the consumption A difficulty with this view is that there seems to be no reason why a numeraire good would have positive value in (and out of) equilibrium.

An alternative way to think of the organization of the market is to imagine that although is no numeraire good with positive value, the consumer has the option not to spend all his wealth. He could conceivably throw away some of his endowment or some of his consumption bundle. Although he is not forced to spend all his wealth, he will in fact do so unless he reaches a satiation point.

It may be argued that the situation is different in a market for contracts without limited The investor holds his wealth in the form of an initial portfolio of contracts. cannot just throw some of the contracts away since they oblige him to make a payment in some situations. The only way he can get rid of some contracts is to exchange in the market for other contacts with the same value. Consequently, his chosen portfolio has to have the same value as his initial portfolio, implying that the budget constraint is an equality.

Side 193

A portfolio e is a direction of improvement for investor i at aj if Vj(aj + te) > V^aJ)
for all t > 0.

Condition 1. Positive semi-independence of directions of improvement: If for each i,
e' is a direction of improvement for investor i at a)', and if S/ e' = 0, then e' = Ofor all i.

The following proposition is proved in the next section.

Proposition 1. Condition I implies the existence of an equality-constrained general
equilibrium.

In order to interpret Condition 1, let a; denote the limiting slope at large values of a or [l of investor Vs indifference curve in (a, /AJ-space through the standard deviation and mean (cr,(a/), to' R') of his initial endowment portfolio. Also, for any portfolio e t^ 0, let a, (e) denote the amount of mean per unit of standard deviation of return to e according to investor i 's beliefs. A portfolio e # 0 is a direction of improvement for / at Jif and only if cti(e) > a,. See Nielsen (1987, 1990b) for details.

If Wj is concave, as assumed by Allingham (1991), then otj = + 00, all / 's indifference
curves have this limiting slope, and there is necessarily satiation. No such assumption
is imposed here.

The following proposition is a direct consequence of Proposition 1 above and Proposition
of Nielsen (1990b).

Proposition 2. Interpretation of Condition 1 and existence of an equality-constrained
equilibrium.

1. Condition 1 is equivalent to the following: If for each i, é is a portfolio with a,(e')
> dj (or é = 0), and if X, el = 0, then el Rl = Ofor all i.

2. If the investors agree on all expected returns, then Condition 1 holds and there
exists an equality constrained general equilibrium.

3. Ifa( = æ for all i, then Condition 1 holds and there exists an equality constrained
general equilibrium.

One might attempt to construct an ordinary general equilibrium from an equalityconstrained equilibrium in the following way. Consider an augmented model with a numeraire good that does not affect preferences. An equality-constrained general in the augmented model corresponds to an ordinary general equilibrium the original model if either the price of the numeraire is positive or it is negative but negative holdings of the numeraire are allowed. However, in the latter case, Condition is violated; and in general, there is no reason why the equality-constrained general price of the numeraire would be different from zero. The main existence below imposes a condition which ensures that an equality-constrained general equilibrium is a general equilibrium without introducing a numeraire good.

From now on, we shall maintain the assumption of homogeneous beliefs:

Assumption 2. Homogeneous beliefs: R' = R and H, =¦ O for all i.

In order to compute and exploit an expression for the gradient of Vh it is useful to

Side 194

introduce some notation. If x is a portfolio, let


DIVL3896

Then y, (x) > 0. The gradient of Vj is


DIVL3900

If (xl) is an allocation, set


DIVL3904

Then y>o. Note that yisa function of the allocation (x1), even though it is sup
pressed in the notation.

An allocation is individually rational if it is attainable and Pareto dominates the ini
tial allocation. Let .4 denote the set of individually rational allocations, i.e.,


DIVL3910

Theorem 1. Existence of general equilibrium in CAPM without a riskless asset. Assume
all assets are risky and that


DIVL3914

for all i and all individually rational allocations. Then there exists a general equili
brium.

Proof: Because the investors have homogeneous beliefs, there exists an equality constrained general equilibrium (p.(x')) by Proposition 2. We shall show that it is ac tually a general equilibrium (except that we may need to replace p by -p). The first order condition for utility maximization implies that there exist numbers A, with


DIVL3920

Divide by y'(x'), sum over /, and multiply by y to get


DIVL3924

where

Side 195

DIVL3928

Since (-p, (x1)) is also an equality-constrained general equilibrium, it may be assumed
loss of generality that A > 0. Now,


DIVL3932

Hence A > 0, and A, > 0 for all /. This implies that V'(xl) and/? point in the same
direction, so that / in fact maximizes utility atx1 subject to an inequality constraint. ?

A special case of the condition in Theorem 1 obtains when


DIVL3938

(1)

at all individually rational allocations and


DIVL3944

(2)

for all / and at all individually rational allocations. Inequality 1 will hold if


DIVL3950

(3)

for all / and at all individually rational allocations (divide by yrfx'), sum over /, and multiply by y). The conditions in the main theorem of Allingham (1991) amount to imposing Inequalities 2 and 3 globally (rather than only at individually rational allocations). 1 ensures that all general equilibrium prices are strictly positive. Thus, Allingham's main result is a special case of Theorem 1.

3. Equality-Constrained General Equilibria

This section explores for existence of equality-constrained general equilibria in an abstract asset market model and proves Proposition 1 in this generalized setting. In fact, we shall prove the existence of a »modified general equilibrium«, which is an equality-constrained general equilibrium where the insatiable investors actually optimize to an inequality budget constraint.

Assets and portfolios are represented as before. There are still m investors / = 1,...
m. Investor / has choice setX1, which is a subset of IR".

Side 196

Assumption 3. The choice set Xis closed and convex.

An investor's preferences among portfolios is represented by his utility function V
for portfolios, which is not necessarily derived from preferences over mean and variance
return.

Assumption 4. The utility function V is continuous and strongly quasi-concave.

By definition, the function V is strongly quasi-concave if V'(tx +(\-t)y) > V'(y)
whenever 0 < t < 1 and x and y are portfolios in X' with V'(x) > V'(y).

Satiation portfolios are defined as before. Say that investor / is satiable if there is a
satiation portfolio for /in X', and call him insatiable otherwise.

An allocation is an w-tuple (x') = (xx...xm) consisting of a portfolio x1 in A"' for
each investor. Each investor / has an initial portfolio <o'.

Assumption 5. For all i, the initial portfolio a)' belongs to the interior of the choice
setX'.

The initial portfolios constitute the initial allocation (co1). An allocation (x1) is attainable
x' =Ii co1.

The concepts of a general equilibrium and an equality-constrained general equilibrium
defined as in the previous section, except that the investors optimize only in
their choice sets A.

A modified general equilibrium is a price vector p ¥^ 0 and an attainable allocation (xl) such that for each satiable investor /, x' is optimal for i subject to the equality budget p'x' = p'aj, while for each insatiable investor /, x' is optimal for / subject to the inequality budget constraint p'x' <p'aj. Formally, p'x' = p'a)', and if y' is a portfolio in X' with VfV) > Vfx1), then/// #/?V if/ is satiable, and/?'/ >pVif / is insatiable.

Obviously, a general equilibrium is a modified general equilibrium, and a modified
general equilibrium is an equality-constrained general equilibrium.

If e is a direction of resession of X' and x is a portfolio in X', say that e is a direction
improvement at x for the investor if Vt (x + te) > Vt (x) for all t > 0.

Condition 1 and Proposition 1 make sense in the present model without adjustment.
The following proposition is stronger and implies Proposition 1.

Proposition 3. Condition 1 implies the existence of a modified general equilibrium.
The proof of proposition 3 requires the following Lemma.

Lemma 1. Assume that each X is bounded below. Then there exists a modified general

Proof: Modify the existence proof in Hart and Kuhn (1975) as follows. There is no production. Hart and Kuhn's Assumptions (a) (y) and (e) hold for all /, and Assumption(8) for insatiable /. For satiable /, ,modify the definition of the demand correspondenceDj, the truncated economy by using an equality as budget constraint insteadof inequality. In the proof of Hart and Kuhn s Theorem 5, note that if all investorsare

Side 197

vestorsaresatiable, then case (b) implies case (a). Hence, what needs to be shown is that case (b) is impossible if at least one investor is insatiable. In the case where/? 'z < 0, note that/?'*' <p'a)' for some insatiable investor /, and proceed to a contradiction. In the case where p 'z = 0, pick an insatiable investor /. The arguments of Hart and Kuhn show that x' lies neither in the interior of T nor on the boundary of T, and hence case (b) is impossible. This establishes the existence of a modified general equilibrium in the truncated economy, and it is straightforward to show that it is also a modified generalequilibrium the original economy, c.f. Hart and Kuhn's Remark 1. ?

The definition of the set A of individually rational allocations from the previous section can be directly applied here. Recall the concept of »Pareto attainable portfolios« Nielsen (1989). A portfolio x is Pareto attainable for investor / if it is part of some individually rational allocation, i.e., it belongs to the set


DIVL3999

where A is the set of individually rational allocations.

Proof of Proposition 3: (Modification of the existence proof in Nielsen (1989)). The set A is closed and convex. Condition 1 implies that A has no non-zero directions of recession, so A is compact, and hence each A1 is compact. For each /, let Nl be a compact, neighborhood of A', and set Yl =X'D N'. Then Y' is convex, compact and contains co' in its interior. Consider the truncated economy where the choise sets X' are replaced by the sets Y'. By Lemma 1, there exists a modified general equilibrium (p,(x')) for the truncated economy. Since (x') is an individually allocation in the truncated it is also an individually rational allocation in the original economy, and so jc' belongs to A1 and to the interior of N' for all /. Using strong quasi-concavity, it is easily seen that (p, (x')) is a modified general equilibrium for the original economy. ?

References

Allingham, M. 1991. Existence Theorems in
the Capital Asset Pricing Model. Econometrica
1169-1174.

Hart, O. D. and H. W. Kuhn. 1975. A Proof of the Existence of Equilibrium Without the Free Disposal Assumption. Journal of Mathematical Economics 2, 335-343.

Nielsen, L. T. 1985. Risk-Taking and Capital
Market Equilibrium. Ph. D. dissertation,
Harvard University.

Nielsen, L. T. 1987. Portfolio Selection in the
Mean-Variance Model: A Note. Journal

ofFinance 42, 1371-1376.

Nielsen, L. T. 1989. Asset Market Equilibrium
Short-Selling. Review of Economic
56, 467-474.

Nielsen, L. T. 1990a. Equilibrium in CAPM
Without a Riskless Asset. Review of Economic
57, 315-324.

Nielsen, L. T. 1990b. Existence of Equilibrium
CAPM. Journal of Economic
Theory 52, 223-231.

Nielsen, L. T. 1992. Positive Prices in CAPM.
To appear in the Journal of Finance.